

Or are they?
Regime Change: Toward a Postliberal Future by Patrick Deneen. Sentinel, 2023. 288 pp., $30.00
During the early days of the Iraq War, I had a colleague who liked to rail against the âneo-cons.â It became apparent while conversing with this educated, intelligent fellow that he had no idea what a neo-conservative was. He was blissfully unaware that first-generation neoconsâpeople like Irving Kristol, Norman Podhoretz, and Nathan Glazerâhad started as leftists, even Marxists, but gradually became skeptical of the progressive enterprise. My colleague was a sociologist with no background in international relations. He also wasnât aware of the second-generation neocon foreign policy theory, which I describe as liberal ends by realist means. Whatever one thinks of that theory, neocon writers such as Bill Kristol and Robert Kagen had a coherent foreign policy vision. Yet for my colleague âneo-conâ simply was an epithet to designate âpeople whose politics I donât like.â
The same has come to pass with more recent terms such as ânational conservativeâ (or ânat-conâ) and âpostliberal.â I have heard and read people using those terms indistinguishably, not realizing that these are two different groupsâalbeit with some theoretical crosspollination. Many of these groupsâ critics barely attempt to grapple with what these two schools of thought have to say. Nor do the critics consider whether their critiques of liberalism have any sound basis. When used by more mainstream conservatives, the terms ânat-conâ and âpostliberalâ have simply become epithets meaning âconservatives we donât like.â
One of the leading postliberals, Patrick Deneenâwho explicitly critiqued national conservatism at a national conservative conferenceârose to prominence with his book Why Liberalism Failed. Touted by Barack Obama as worthy of a close read when the book came out in 2018, Why Liberalism Failed has a basic thesis: Liberalism has a bad anthropology. Liberalismâs false view of humanity posits the individual as an isolated, unencumbered bearer of rights who seeks the maximum fulfillment of desires. A sound liberal government, then, promotes radical autonomy and material comfort. Taken to its logical conclusions, liberalism produces a crude consumerism and a destruction of tradition-bearing institutions such as church and family. It leaves in its wake deracinated individuals, struggling to find meaning or a coherent narrative of life, reduced to pawns of big business and big government alike. Liberalism, argued Deneen, is at its worst when it is most itself.
This really shouldnât be a controversial contention. In many ways it tracks the arguments of Alexis de Tocqueville writing in the 1830s. Democracy uproots people. It erodes familial, geographical, and religious ties. It promotes an excessive interest in material comfort and unending progress, producing in the end a particular kind of democratic despotism. This, warns Tocqueville, is what happens if a nation embraces an unalloyed form of democracy. That is why he stresses that democracy must preserve at least some of aristocracyâs virtuesâsuch as an appreciation of beauty and greatness, and a sense of historical continuity linking us to both the past and future. Tocqueville warns against excessive centralization while extolling the virtues of American religion, associations, local government, andâit should be notedâAmerican women. As with Deneen and liberalism, Tocqueville says democracy is at its worst when it is most itself. One can see echoes of this argument in the thought of one of Deneenâs friendly critics, the late Peter Lawler, in his âbuilding better than they knewâ thesis.
One criticism of Why Liberalism Failed was that it was almost all critique, no solution. There was the obligatory âWhere do we go from here?â at the end of the book, but it, frankly, felt tacked on. Regime Change: Toward a Postliberal Future is a response to this criticism. Those interested in smart, engaging, thoughtful critiques of the liberal project should read both books. Then, at least, one can make an intelligent critique of postliberalism.
Deneen begins Regime Change with an overview of the previous workâs appraisal of liberalism. He focuses specifically on the thought of John Stuart Mill and the famous âharm principleâ Mill articulates in On Liberty. Deneen argues that this thin definition of liberty, the right to do what you want as long as no one is harmed, sets the stage for âthe end of liberalism.â Mill ignores the cultivation of virtue in the name of accentuating individual liberation. He also expresses a contempt for any authority outside the self and values transgression for its own sake.
Yet, opines Deneen, it is custom and authoritative cultural institutions that protect the average person against the rapaciousness of the elite. In Deneenâs view, the emphasis on the autonomous self to the detriment of custom and communal authority has left people adrift. Without these authoritative cultural transmitters of meaning and custom, the common person becomes a pawn to a âpower eliteâ that promises to manage peopleâs lives for them. One detects a strong scent of Tocquevilleâs democratic despotism here. Deneen argues that both the American left and the market-oriented right have bought into this theory.
Deneen next offers a taxonomy of contemporary politics. He creates a rubric based on whether one sees the common people (or proletariat) as essentially revolutionary or conservative, and whether one believes in government by some kind of elite or largely by the people. This allows Deneen to create a kind of Punnett square of political opinions. Deneen favors the lower right quadrant of his chart, which sees the people as conservative (i.e., defenders of custom) who uphold rule by the people. He posits Edmund Burke and Benjamin Disraeli as the foremost defenders of what he names âcommon good conservatism.â
Such a conservatism puts elites on the side of the customs and habits of the common people, unlike the Millian progressive liberals, who view the people as reactionaries whose traditions must be eroded in the name of âprogressâ and âliberation.â But this conservatism also has a faith in the peoplesâ ability to governâsomething classical liberals (like Locke) distrusted because they assumed the people would attack property. The Marxists likewise distrusted this ability of the people, as they believed the people were trapped by false consciousness. Both camps thought that elites should rule. In the view of classical liberals, rule should occur through complex governing systems that render impotent any move against accumulation of vast amounts of property. In the case of the Marxists, rule should happen via a revolutionary vanguard. Common good conservatism, by contrast, seeks âstability, order, and continuityâ as a defense of the people against attempts by elites to subvert norms that protect the people against rapacious elites. So what changes are needed to achieve these aims?
For one, Deneen proposes reviving a mixed constitution. One source for this notion is Thomas Aquinas. In Deneenâs words, Aquinas saw the people âas forming the base of a moral order, and elites responsible for protecting and deepening the core virtues of âthe manyâ embedded in a culture of common sense. A âmixingâ came about as the result of a leadership class that saw its primary role as the defender of bottom-up custom as the ground condition of human flourishing.â
The many largely govern themselves âthrough the development of âcustomââ while elites, âacceptable and even chosen by the many,â govern with âconsiderable deference to the settled customs of the people.â In practice, drawing from Disraeli, Deneen seems to mean that in general the people have power, but under the mixed regime they would not use their power to attack the elite in some kind of revolutionary fervor. Likewise, the elites, whose rule is in some sense inevitable, would not wield power with their own interests in mind (especially their own enrichment) but with a strong respect for the ways and habits of the common people. This virtuous elite is labeled by Deneen âAristopopulismââa truly virtuous ruling class that respects and protects the interests and manners of the average people. Such an elite would not be the crude, vulgar elite that we have today.Â
Deneen concludes with a call for different kinds of integration to combat various disintegrations promoted in modern, liberal thought. For example, Deneen advances a notion of solidarityâthe sense that we all have our parts to play and we should play them well. This idea draws on John Winthropâs famous âModell of Christian Charityâ (itself influenced by 1 Corinthians 12): while some people will have more âeliteâ positions and other more seemingly mundane, all social positions deserve respect and encouragement to see themselves as contributing to the common good. Again, Deneen sees such mutual respect among classes as a check upon the voraciousness of the elites.
Deneen also discusses racism, rightly noting that often the defense of tradition and custom in the United States was âbound upâ with defenses of racism. Deneen, similar to Wendell Berryâs most recent work, argues that black and white working classes have more in common than they are often led to believe. Deneen believes that emphasis on âsystemic racismâ robs blacks of moral agency while stoking (purposefully?) further racial distrust. Echoing his defense of solidarity, Deneen believes an emphasis on what we all have in common, rather than stressing our differences, would go far in promoting racial healing. He goes on to defend a robust localism (rather than nationalism), a public respect for religion, and a great attention to continuity rather than a worship of amorphous âprogress.â
Deneen is a fine writer. I confess some sympathy with his cause. He presents a thoughtful, insightful, and well-articulated counternarrative to the dominant American discourse. Deneen is right to perceive that the liberal foundations of our order are weakening. The time is ripe for serious reconsideration of fundamental ideas. Still, Deneen has some philosophical and rhetorical tendencies that weaken his argument. I will mention just two.
First, Deneen at times makes grand statements with little to no evidence. As with Why Liberalism Failed, I found myself peppering my copy of Regime Change with marginal notations such as âe.g.?â, âexample?â, and âevidence?â Just a few illustrations will do. Deneen states early in the book: âAs the second decade of the twenty-first century began, a new political alignment and division came to define the Western (and even global) landscape: the elites against the people, populists against the new aristocracy.â This is true, but Deneenâs readers would be well-served by a couple of examples that help flesh out the point. Later Deneen writes, âThe managerial elite is arguably the first ruling class that actively rejects appeal to a shared well of common experience and practiceâ and that Millâs âdeep hostility to traditional society remains a powerful and even dominant viewpoint among progressives.â Is there no data or anecdote that Deneen could include here to support these bold, controversial claims? Finally, can Deneen offer evidence that the common people actually support and live in the kind of traditional, customary manner he associates with them? One cannot make these kinds of sweeping claims without offering supporting evidence.
Second, and relatedly, Deneen tends to turn liberalism into a caricature in order to bolster his appraisal. Deneenâs liberalism is often a straw man. He curiously argues that classical liberalism âis especially suspicious of majoritarian democracy,â doubting âthe governing abilitiesâ of âordinary people.â Thus, the calls to ârestrain participation in politics, whether institutionally or informally.â There are few political thinkers in human history that do not, to some degree or another, share this view. It is not unique to liberalism.
From Plato to Alexis de Tocqueville (see his anxiety over tyranny of the majority) to Abraham Lincoln (see his Lyceum Address) many consequential political observers understood that the people can abuse power. It is that dastardly liberal James Madison who says, accurately, âA dependence on the people is, no doubt, the primary control on the government; but experience has taught mankind the necessity of auxiliary precautions.â The idea that respect for the people is necessary but insufficient for good government, is ubiquitous in the history of political thought. Similarly, Deneen exaggerates the agreement between âfirst waveâ liberals (i.e., classical liberals) and âsecond waveâ liberals (i.e., progressive liberals). At least in the American context, Progressives of the early twentieth century quite consciously jettisoned the political science of the liberal founding, rejecting natural rights, limited government, and separation of powers (see the political science of Woodrow Wilson and Herbert Croly for examples). Deneen strains to posit more harmony than actually exists, to the denigration of the American founding. He exaggerates classical liberalismâs defense of economic inequality, ignoring its dedication to a more fundamental natural equality. Finally both Carlo Lancellotti, in his work on Augusto Del Noce, and Deneenâs postliberal running mate Adrian Vermeule have a better, more thorough takes on the symbiosis between liberalism, capitalism, and Marxist revolutionary thought.
As a political thinker Patrick Deenen is both inspiring and frustrating. He has a keen intellect and a true gift for communication. Still, his tendency to favor polemics over thoughtful, careful presentation sometimes causes him to appear more extreme and intemperate than he really is. Regime Change is a delightful, informative read. Like Deneenâs opponents, especially on the Right, Deneen should realize there is plenty in the world to criticize. One need not invent strawmen when men in the flesh abound. There are liberal virtues along with liberal vices. Granted, there are premodern antecedents to many of liberalismâs virtues, but these premodern goods tended to enter the American bloodstream via a liberalism mixed with Christianity. A more thoughtful presentation would recognize this fact.
Still, if one wants a stimulating, thought-provoking alternative to the American political conventional wisdom, Regime Change is the book for you. Deneen is surely correct that there is something in the air that suggests a rethinking of our basic political order is overdue. Warts and all, Regime Change is a valuable contribution to that rethinking.
Jon D. Schaff of Professor of Political Science at Northern State University in Aberdeen, South Dakota. Heâs the author of Abraham Lincolnâs Statesmanship and the Limits of Liberal Democracy and co-author of Age of Anxiety: Meaning, Identity, and Politics in 21st Century Film and Literature.
Many thanks for this review. I learned a lot from it.
As good a response to the book as any I’ve read!
What do advocates of “rule by the people” such as (the very Catholic) Deneen do with things like abortion? This morning’s AP email includes another poll–confirming that aroud 2/3 of Americans want abortion legal, but with restrictions. Around a quarter say it should always be legal; only about 1 in 10 say it should always be illegal?
These are the same numbers we’ve seen since the 1970s on this question; if any difficult moral question has a policy solution grounded in the customs of the American people, it’s this moderate position that the majority of them espouse.
I’m not advocating for that; I’m just wondering what the applauders of the prudence of the people make of that?
Thanks Jon. Very helpful review. My own query would be: Isn’t it more correct to say that neo-liberalism (as opposed to liberalism classically and broadly understood) has failed? I’m drawn to the idea of a communitarian liberalism (a phrase uttered a few days ago by Yascha Mounk in his interview with Michael Walzer): prioritizing the rights of the individual while at the same time recognizing the individual as inextricable from all sorts of communities and associations.